front |1 |2 |3 |4 |5 |6 |7 |8 |9 |10 |11 |12 |13 |14 |15 |16 |17 |18 |19 |20 |21 |22 |23 |24 |25 |26 |27 |28 |review |
B. An Expanded Sphere of
International Health Law: The Influence of Trade and the Human Right
to Health
Although international law
under WHO’s auspices is sparse, there is a much larger body of
international law that powerfully affects global health in areas
ranging from food safety, arms control, and the environment to trade
and human rights. The WHO should be a leader in creating, or at
least influencing, these norms, but that has not happened. The
agency has shied away from the “high politics” of international law
because it has seen itself principally as a scientific, technical
agency. Thus, WHO is comfortable developing technical standards for
food safety under the Codex Alimentarius Commission, but it has not
ventured into the harder terrain of WTO rule making and dispute
resolution. It ought to have a great deal to contribute, and have
some sway over, matters of trade in goods and services; sanitary and
phytosanitary measures; and intellectual property rights in vaccines
and medicines. Yet, its influence is nowhere to be found.
It might not matter whether
WHO was a prime mover on matters of global health if extant
international norms were adequate, but they are not. International
institutions and social activists increasingly have turned to the
language of human rights to articulate their fondest dreams for
global health. And, the international right to health resonates with
bold-sounding obligations for the “highest attainable standard of
physical and mental health.” The WHO Constitution defines health so
broadly to be simply unachievable: “a state of complete physical,
mental and social well-being.”
These high-minded
declarations have had little normative force, as they lack the basic
features of a “right”: What exactly does the right entail and what
obligations do States, and others, have to conform? When is the
right violated? And what are the mechanisms to enforce the
entitlement? Despite considerable progress, recasting the problem of
extremely poor health as a human rights violation does not help for
a number of reasons. First, the legal obligation falls primarily on
each State to “respect, protect, and fulfill” the right to health
for its own population. Although the ICESCR posits that all States
have duties to assist and cooperate in achieving economic and social
rights, the obligation to assist other States’ populations cannot
become primary. Second, the right to health itself is expressed as
“progressively realizable,” so there can be little agreement as to
when a State has breached an obligation to its people, let alone to
people in far away places. Finally, even if some obligation to offer
financial and technical assistance could be read into human rights
instruments, there is no systematic method of implementation and
enforcement. This leaves us with the very problem posited in this
Lecture—the duty to improve the health of the world’s most
disadvantaged people falls primarily on those who lack the means to
do so. This is undoubtedly an untenable position if global health is
to be taken as a serious issue of international concern.
|